Taken from an excellent Candide site
Tout est bien / All is good
This article is taken from Voltaire's Philosophical Dictionary, first published in 1764.
It shows that, even after
the publication of Candide, the philosophe continued to think about and to criticize the
notion of optimism.
As in Candide, Voltaire here uses humor to great effect, but he addresses the arguments of
his adversaries more
directly. For this reason, the article may be useful for clarifying certain aspects of the
conte.
This translation is taken from Voltaire, Philosophical Dictionary, edited and translated
by Theodore Besterman
(London and New York: Penguin Books, 1972), p. 68-74.
There was a fine row in the schools, and even among people who think, when Leibniz,
paraphrasing Plato, built
his edifice of the best of possible worlds, and imagined that all was for the best. He
affirmed in the north of
Germany that god could make only a single world. Plato had at least left him free to make
five, because there are
only five regular solids: the tetrahedron or three-faced pyramid with uniform base, the
cube, the hexahedron, the
dodecahedron, the icosahedron. But our world is not shaped like any of Plato's five
bodies, he had allowed god a
sixth manner.
That will do for Plato. Leibniz, who was certainly a better geometer than he, and a more
profound metaphysician,
did mankind the service of explaining that we ought to be entirely satisfied, and that god
could do no more for us,
that he had necessarily chosen, among all the possibilities, what was undeniably the best
one.
"What will become of original sin?" they shouted at him. "It will become
what it can," said Leibniz and his friends;
but in public he wrote that original sin was necessarily part of the best of worlds.
What! to be chased from a place of delights, where we would have lived for ever if an
apple had not been eaten!
What! produce in wretchedness wretched children who will suffer everything, who will make
others suffer
everything! What! to undergo every illness, feel every sorrow, die in pain, and for
refreshment be burned in the
eternity of centuries! Is this really the best lot that was available? This is not too
good for us; and how can it be
good for good?
Leibniz realized that these questions were unanswerable: so he wrote thick books in which
he did not agree with
himself.
A Lucullus in good health, dining well with his friends and his mistress in the house of
Apollo, can say laughingly
that there is no devil; but let him put his head out of the window and he will see unhappy
people; let him suffer a
fever and he will be unhappy himself.
I do not like to quote; it is usually a ticklish job: what precedes and follows the
passage quoted is passed over,
and one exposes oneself to a thousand quarrels. Still, I must quote Lactantius, church
father, who, in his chapter
XIII, of his On the Wrath of God puts these words into the mouth of Epicurus:
Either god wants to remove the evil from this world, and cannot, or he can, and does not
want to; or
he neither wants to nor can; or he wants to and can. If he wants to but cannot, this is
impotence,
which is contrary to the nature of god; if he can but does not want to, this is
wickedness, which is no
less contrary to his nature; if he neither can nor wants to this is at once wickedness and
impotence; if
he wants to and can (which is the only one of these possibilities fitting for god) whence
then comes
the evil which is on earth?
The argument is powerful; so that Lactantius answers it very badly, saying that god wants
evil but that he has given
us the wisdom with which one acquires the good. It must be admitted that this answer is
quite weak in comparison
with the objection, for it assumes that god could create wisdom only by producing evil;
besides our wisdom is
pretty ridiculous!
Bolingbroke, Shaftesbury and Pope, who embodied their ideas, do not resolve the question
any better than the
others: their All is good means nothing more than that all is controlled by immutable
laws. Who does not know
that? You tell us nothing new when you observe, as all little children have done, that
flies are born to be eaten by
spiders, spiders by swallows, swallows by shrikes, shrikes by eagles, eagles to be killed
by men, men to kill one
another, and to be eaten by worms, and then, all but one in a thousand, by devils.
Here we have a clear and fixed order among every kind of animal. There is order
everywhere. When a stone is
formed in my bladder it is by means of admirable mechanics: calculous juices pass little
by little into my blood,
they filter into the kidneys, pass through the ureters, deposit themselves in my bladder,
and assemble there by an
excellent Newtonian attraction; the stone is formed, gets bigger, I suffer pains a
thousand times worse than death,
by the most elegant arrangement in the world. A surgeon, having perfected the art invented
by Tubalcain, comes
to thrust a sharp and cutting iron into the perineum, and takes hold of my stone with his
pincers. It breaks under
his efforts by a necessary mechanism; and by the same mechanism I die in frightful
torments. All this is good, all
this is the evident consequence of inalterable physical principles. I agree with them, and
I knew it as well as you
did.
If we were without feeling there would be no reason to object to this cause and effect.
But this is not the point.
We are inquiring whether there are any perceptible evils, and whence they come.
"There are no evils," says Pope
in his fourth essay on the All is good; "or if there are particular evils, they form
the common good."
A strange general good! composed of the stone, the gout, all crimes, all suffering, death
and damnation.
The fall of man is the platter we stick on all there particular diseases of the body and
the soul, which are called
"general health". But Shaftesbury and Bolingbroke derided original sin; Pope
does not refer to it; it is obvious that
their system undermines the Christian religion at its foundations, and explains nothing at
all.
Nevertheless this system has recently been approved by several theologians who readily
accept contradictions.
Capital! we must not begrudge anybody the consolation of reasoning as best he can about
the deluge of evils by
which we are inundated. It is right to allow the incurable to eat what they like. It has
even been claimed that this
system is consoling. "God," says Pope, "sees perish with equal eye the hero
and the sparrow, an atom or a
thousand planets precipitated into ruin, the formation of a soap-bubble or a world."
Here, I must admit, we have a pleasant consolation. Do you not find a great palliative in
the prescription of lord
Shaftesbury, who says that god is not going to upset his eternal laws for so puny an
animal as man? It must at least
be admitted that this puny animal has the right to cry out humbly, and to seek to
understand, in crying, why these
eternal laws are not made for the well-being of every individual.
This system of All is good represents the author of nature only as a powerful and
maleficent king, who does not
care, so long as he carries out his plan, that it costs four or five hundred thousand men
their lives, and that the
others drag out their days in want and in tears.
So far from the notion of the best of possible worlds being consoling, it drives to
despair the philosophers who
embrace it. The problem of good and evil remains an inexplicable chaos for those who seek
in good faith. It is an
intellectual exercise for those who argue: they are convicts who play with their chains.
As for the unthinking mass,
it rather resembles fish who have been moved from a river to a reservoir. They do not
suspect that they are there
to be eaten in lent: nor do we know anything by our own resources about the causes of our
destiny.
Let us put at the end of nearly all chapters on metaphysics the two letters used by Roman
judges when they could
not understand a lawsuit: N. L., non liquet, this is not clear.